Freedom of speech, identity and offence
In a 'news analysis' article for Tuesday’s Belfast Telegraph, I
examined the tensions which can exist between identity politics and free speech. It focussed mostly on arguments around gender
identity, and speakers being banned from university debates, but it also
touched upon the issue of same-sex marriage, which is so topical and incendiary
in Northern Ireland.
Maybe the timing of the piece was unfortunate, because there
was a lot of anger around on Tuesday morning and justifiably so.
On Monday, in spite of a majority of MLAs in the Stormont Assembly
backing a motion to introduce same-sex marriage here, it was defeated, because
the DUP tabled a ‘petition of concern’. This mechanism requires a majority from both designations
in the Assembly to vote in favour of a measure, if it’s to pass. Petitions of concern were intended to protect
minority rights, but they have been used instead as vetoes on any matters which
cause disagreement.
My article got caught up in the ensuing crossfire on social
media. Some commenters thought it apologised
for the DUP, a few interpreted it as an endorsement of arguments against
same-sex marriage and others reckoned it attacked transgender people. I got accused of being a ‘fundamentalist’, ‘in
hoc to the DUP’ and, most strangely of all, ‘a tool of Zionists’. All good fun.
These reactions prompted me to have some rather sniffy and unnecessary
thoughts about falling standards of English comprehension. They also made me want to add some reflections
on the nature of freedom of speech and associated modern attitudes. After
all, this ‘right’ is usually still thought to underpin our democracy.
So here they are:
The right to freedom of speech is not
absolute. I touched upon this in my article, but
what does it mean in practice? Our right to speak
freely is curtailed by things like defamation law and ‘hate speech’
legislation. There are also laws around
decency, broadcasting regulations, copyright and a host of other limitations,
depending on your preferred mode of expression.
There are all sorts of contentious arguments about the balance between free
speech and the law. However, the point
is that restrictions are generally pretty specific. Yet, the words ‘hate speech’ are often bandied
around to criticise a contentious argument, without reference to laws drafted
in statute or their interpretation in courts.
Freedom of speech doesn’t depend upon
you agreeing with the argument. It’s
easy to champion free speech for people with whom you agree. It’s harder to stick up for the principle
when you think that the person speaking is wrong, sometimes grievously so. Or, to turn that around, supporting someone’s
freedom to speak certainly does not mean that you endorse their argument. It doesn’t even mean that you don’t find it
ridiculous, hateful or repellent.
Freedom of speech doesn’t depend upon your approval
of the person who is speaking. Disapproving
of someone is not reason enough to deprive them of their right to speak. So many arguments, about almost any
controversial issue, seem to revolve around who is saying something rather than
what they are saying. “So and so shouldn’t
get a platform because they are a ‘phobe’, an ‘evangelical’, a ‘fundamentalist’,
a ‘bigot’”. All these descriptions may
(or may not) be true, but they are irrelevant to arguments around free speech. Of course, there is a certain significance to
giving someone a platform to speak. It
isn’t always appropriate. But, at fora
like universities and public debates, surely the presumption must be that, if
someone isn’t breaking the law by expressing their opinion, then they can be heard
and challenged? And again, being prepared
to listen to someone doesn’t imply any kind of approval.
Freedom of speech doesn’t mean all opinions
are valid. The concept of freedom of
speech does not mean that everyone’s views are equal, or worthwhile, or that
anyone is under an obligation to listen.
That’s the sort of misconception that pits doctors against homeopaths in
debates about medicine, or scientists against Jeremy Clarkson, discussing
climate change. The flipside of people who want to silence anyone they don’t like, is the ‘I’m entitled to my opinion’
brigade. Yes, you are entitled to your
opinion, but the rest of us are equally entitled to point out that it’s
worthless, because you don’t know what you’re talking about. We’re even entitled to point and laugh!
There is no right not to be offended. This actually might be the central point. With more than 1,100 words to flesh out my
thoughts and more time, it would’ve been nice to explain what I meant by ‘identity
politics’ and the corrosive effect this notion can have. To be really short: the idea seems to have taken hold
that particular groups of people, or individuals within those groups, who define themselves by certain categories – gender,
sex, race, nationality, religion, culture and more – get to decide what offends
them and the rest of society then has a duty not to give offence. There’s a very good article in The Times
today, by the columnist David Aaronovitch, examining how this works practically. On certain university campuses student unions are
doing ‘risk assessments’ on all potential speakers, in case any
students may feel “threatened or unsafe”. Now, it’s absolutely right to take people’s sensitivities into account and
to attempt, insofar as possible, not to cause offence. However, we can't apply a completely subjective definition of 'offensiveness'. It is not enough to say that someone has been offended, so therefore someone else has said something offensive. If discussing ideas and debating issues
cause our students to feel ‘threatened and unsafe’, then they should try to
become more robust, or stay away from academia!
Rantier than I’d expected, but it’s good to vent once in a while. It is my right after all! Not that anyone is obliged to listen.
Comments